Sex,
Lies & Feminism
by
Peter Zohrab
Appendix: |
Women's
This, Women's That, and Women's The Other Thing: Historical Manifestations
of Feminism |
1999
Version
1. |
Introduction:
This
chapter gives a brief survey of some historical forms of Feminism, which
has also been known as the Women's Liberation Movement, or the Women's
Movement. The only difference between these terms is that the word "Feminism"
is sometimes used to refer purely to a theory or ideology, whereas the
terms "Women's Movement" and "Women's Liberation Movement" also refer to
political activities.
My
survey does not claim to be complete or up-to-date. In particular, the
Internet and the rise of the international Men's/Fathers' Movement may
well have had impacts on international Feminism that future historians
and writers will be in a better position to look back on than I am now.
My aim is simply to indicate most of the main themes and claims of Feminism
over the last couple of centuries, so as to give a context for the issues
which I have raised in earlier chapters -- and for others which I hope
to raise in future books.
|
2. |
What
is Feminism?
Rendall
("The Origins of Modern Feminism: Women in Britain, France and the United
States, 1780-1860," London:Macmillan, 1985) states that the word "Feminism"
was first used in English in 1894. It was derived from the French word
"feminisme", which was apparently invented by the French Utopian Socialist,
Charles Fourier.
I
would like to attempt a definition of Feminism which covers all the "Feminisms"
which are mentioned in this chapter -- and perhaps even some that are not.
Feminists seem to have some difficulty in defining Feminism -- mostly,
no doubt, because Feminism has conquered Western societies so thoroughly,
that there are few non-Feminists left here for Feminists to contrast themselves
with. Groups usually define themselves in relation to non-members, and
as this particular group can find few articulate non-members, it ends up
with a fuzzy self-image. I hope to be of assistance in this regard, as
this book is centred around the thesis that the victims-of-oppression model
fits the situation of men at least as well as it fits the situation of
women, and that men's oppressors are the Feminists -- and some overly chivalrous
males.
Another
problem for anyone who wants to define "Feminim" is that, as each generation
of Feminist wins their battles and retires, the next generation comes along
with a completely new set of worries, complaints and demands. These different
generations tend to define themselves in terms of their own current policy
goals. This confuses any attempt at getting an overview of this entire
political movement.
"A
central problem within feminist discourse has been our inability to either
arrive at a consensus of opinion about what feminism is or accept definition(s)
that could serve as points of unification. Without agreed upon definition(s),
we lack a sound foundation on which to construct theory or engage in overall
meaningful praxis." (Hooks "Feminist Theory: From Margin to Center" Boston:South
End Press, 1989,17)
This
uncertainty about the essence of Feminism is one of the hallmarks of Postmodern
Feminism (see below). Previously, Feminists did not find it quite so hard
to define Feminism. The textbook on Feminism by the Bristol Women's Studies
Group (1979), for example, despite declaring itself unable to give a neat
definition of the academic discipline of Women's Studies itself, gives
the following definition of its subject-matter, Feminism. I consider this
an excellent definition, and my own definition is very similar.
"By
feminism we mean both an awareness of women's position in society as one
of disadvantage or inequality compared with that of men, and also a desire
to remove those disadvantages." (Bristol Women's Studies Group "Half the
Sky: An Introduction to Women's Studies,"1979, p. 3)
A
non-Feminist might feel that that definition demonstrated a fairly rational
turn of mind -- one that left the door open for lucid discussion about
whether it was actually true to say that women's position in society was
one of disadvantage or inequality. The desire to remove those disadvantages
and inequalities would presumably disappear if it was agreed, after a period
of dialogue between Feminists and non-Feminists, that they did not, in
fact, exist.
Contrast
the mentality that is implicit in the following, however:
"If
feminism is broadly defined as the quest for a sexually just society, many
people share at least some of its goals, though they disavow the label."
Meehan ("British Feminism from the 1960s to the 1980s". In Smith (ed.)
1990, p. 189).
The
problem with that definition is that it simply takes for granted, rather
than overtly stating, what the previous definition claimed, i.e. that women's
position in society is one of disadvantage vis-a-vis men. A Feminist is
one who (as the very word suggests) is primarily, if not exclusively, interested
in pushing the female point of view and women's agendas. To simply assume
that this is the same as promoting sexual justice betrays a one-sided frame
of mind which would find constructive dialogue with non-Feminists virtually
impossible.
A
good definition of a Feminist appeared in a leaflet advertising the Public
Sessions of the 1993 National Conference of the New Zealand Women's Electoral
Lobby (WEL), in Wellington, New Zealand:
"WEL
defines a feminist as someone who believes that women are socially and
economically disadvantaged because of their gender and acts on that belief."
Here
is another interesting view of Feminism:
"Feminism
is not, in my view, a set of a priori answers, nor a commitment to a particular
ideology. It is rather a willingness to follow questions wherever they
lead us. Feminism insists upon a commitment to listening with open ears
to women's experience in order to reformulate our actions and thought.
It is thus more a method for creative inquiry than a set of predetermined
points. Feminism is a commitment to women's well-being, to pursuing justice
instead of patriarchy, but the substance of women's well-being is not necessarily
known in advance." (Pellauer: "Moral Callousness and Moral Sensitivity:
Violence against Women", in Andolsen et al. 1987, p. 34)
Although
there is a lot I can agree with in that passage, it seems to me to embody
a misconception as to the nature of ideology. Other ideologies, such as
Marxism, are just as open-ended as Feminism -- tending to determine what
questions are asked by its adherents, rather than providing all of the
answers ready-made. That is why there are so many versions of Marxism,
and that is also why there can be theoretical debate about the proper Marxist
approach to many issues.
I
am sure that Feminism has always, by and large, followed questions wherever
they happened to lead -- but the point is that Feminist ideology determines
what questions get asked in the first place. This book is all about pointing
out the inherent bias in the types of questions that Feminists always ask,
and it is also about suggesting other questions that could and should be
asked, as well.
Feminists,
as Pellauer points out, listen to women's experience with open ears. By
the same token, they do not listen to men's experience with open ears.
That is one clear indication of the bias that is inherent in Feminist ideology.
As Pellauer points out, Feminism is a commitment to women's well-being
-- but (by implication) not a commitment to men's well-being. If there
is ever a conflict between men's well-being and women's well-being, there
is no doubt at all what side of the fence Feminists are on.
My
own approach to the definition problem is to define Feminism as the
application of the "victims of oppression" model to the situation of women
in society. Thus a Feminist is one who believes that this model (in
any given society) fits the situation of women more appropriately than
it does the situation of men. This does not imply that all Feminists believe
that the "oppressors" of women are men -- some Feminists believe that the
real oppressor is Society itself, and that men, too, are oppressed by the
rigidity of the roles that Society forces them to adopt.
That
would suffice as a definition, in my opinion. However, one could add that
Feminists are almost bound to be gendercentric and unable to see any ways
in which men are discriminated against or oppressed. So Feminism is really
a state of mind, which means that it is unlikely to die out because of
a lack of issues to campaign on. If the issues didn't exist, then they
would have to be invented (as French writer Voltaire said about God).
|
3. |
Individualist/Liberal
Feminism
Individualist
Feminism received its first substantial formulation in Mary Wollstonecraft's
A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792). This was in the tradition
of 18th century Individualist social and political theory, deriving ultimately
from John Locke's Second Treatise of Government (1689).
Charvet
("Feminism" London:Dent, 1982) describes Individualism as
"the
view that understands the basis of social and political order to lie in
the possession by individuals of rights.... the primary content of the
rights is generally understood to consist in the freedom of individuals
to do what they wish without being interfered with by others" (pp 6-7).
Wollstonecraft
said that, when one referred to "people" or "humans", it was always men
that one meant. Women were viewed principally in relation to men, i.e.
as sexual partners and rearers of men's children, and so on. She said that
women must be looked on primarily as people in their own right, and only
secondarily as the housekeepers and wives, etc. of men.
Wollstonecraft
based this claim or demand on the fact that women (like men) were superior
to animals, in that they are rational creatures. She said that it was irrelevant
that men might be better at doing some things than women were. As long
as women were rational, she claimed, then they were capable of governing
themselves. Men differed in their talents, but this was not used (by liberal
democrats, anyway) as an argument against equal political rights for all
men.
She
did not, of course, agree that women were generally less talented than
men. Her point was that even people who thought women were less talented
should agree that they should have their full rights as human beings.
An
important theme in A Vindication of the Rights of Woman is that men used
education to train girls to play the dependent "womanly" roles that men
have mapped out for them. This, indeed, is a recurrent theme throughout
the Feminist literature.
Wollstonecraft
demands equality of civil rights between men and women. She does not say
much about political rights for women, though there are indications that
she had intended to write something on that topic, too.
J.S.Mill's
The Subjection of Women was an important 19th Century Feminist work, written
under the influence of his late wife, Harriet Taylor. Mill's basic Philosophy
was Utilitarianism, where ethical priority was accorded to the greatest
good of the greatest number of people.
According
to most authorities on Mill's works, the notion of "equality", which is
so basic to Feminist writings in general, did not seem to obviously follow
from Utilitarian principles. Mill had to add it on, as it were, in order
to construct his Feminist argument. Nevertheless, he does try to show that
beneficial results would flow from granting women legal equality with men.
What
he does is to argue that the liberation of women will result in a net gain
in the quantity of happiness for mankind. This is because the "servitude"
of women in marriage makes many women miserable.
He
also says that mankind (by which he meant, in present day Feminist parlance,
"humankind", of course) will benefit if woman's full potential is freed,
educated, and employed to the benefit of all. And marriages would be happier
if men and women were equally well educated. This was because happiness
in marriage depended on the partners being as similar and unified as possible.
Mill's
proposals are similar to those of Wollstonecraft. But he goes further,
in that he says women should have the vote. As far as employment is concerned,
he too says that women should be free to enter the occupation of their
choice (including marriage and child-rearing, if that is their preferred
option).
In
response to the objection that women did not have the same capabilities
as men, he too says that this appears to be the case only because of the
way that they are brought up. If they were brought up in the same way that
men are, then they would be just as capable. In addition to this hypothetical
argument, he also says that women are already obviously capable enough
at a wide variety of tasks in order to justify their wider employment.
In
the course of the nineteenth century, the Feminists registered great gains
in Western countries, as regards educational opportunities in schools and
universities and the admission of women to the professions. Laws relating
to divorce, the property rights of married women, and control of children
in marriage were also modified in a direction that favoured women.
By
the early 20th Century, at the latest, women gained the franchise in most
Western countries. The first breakthrough for the Feminists came in 1869,
when women got the vote in the American State of Wyoming, and the first
sovereign state to grant women the vote was New Zealand -- in 1893. The
first European country to enfranchise women was Finland -- in 1906.
After
the franchise for women had been achieved in many countries, the Second
World War intervened. This caused a hiatus in the Feminists' political
struggles, since they presumably did not want to be forced to serve as
front-line soldiers, as might logically be expected of them if they started
agitating in a wartime political atmosphere. And when the war was over,
people had to be given time to forget the men who had lost their lives
and/or limbs in the War. Coole ("Women in Political Theory" Sussex: Wheatsheaf
Books, 1988, p. 234) characterises this hiatus as a "resurgence of anti-feminist
ideas and practices". But sure enough, after a decent interval, a peacetime
mentality soon evolved in Western societies, to which the hypocrisy of
some of the Feminist demands for "equality" did not seem so glaringly obvious.
In
this post-war era, Feminism's "Second Wave", it seemed natural to focus
more and more on the way that women's role in the family prevented them
from having careers to the extent that men did. This attitude implied that
the roles of wife and mother were somehow inferior to that of income-earner
in a workplace (or wage-slave in the rat-race, as others might phrase it).
One
book that pushed this line within the Individualist Feminist tradition
was Betty Friedan's The Feminine Mystique (1965), which followed relatively
closely on the heels of Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex (1953) (see
below). Friedan's aim was for society and women's lives to be organised
in such a way as to maximise the ability of women to have a career as well
as a family. She thought that American middle-class, suburban, white, heterosexual
housewives were bound to feel unfulfilled and bored, unless they had a
full-time job outside the home. This would, of course, not be such a problem
in countries and classes where labour-saving devices were unaffordable.
"...
Betty Friedan's 1963 book, The Feminine Mystique, was in some ways less
'radical' than Wollstonecraft's, Taylor's or Mill's. Despite Friedan's
implicit understanding of woman as a powerless sex class, she often wrote
as if individual women can, through sheer effort, advance to the ranks
of the powerful sex class known as 'man'. Her tendency, at least in The
Feminine Mystique, was to forget that this is easier said than done, so
long as men are generally in charge of hiring and promoting." (Tong 1989,
22)
Tong
criticises Friedan's book for not being analytical enough to look for societal
barriers to women's achieving careers outside the home. But then, many
years later, Friedan wrote a second book, The Second Stage, which filled
this gap, to some extent:
"In
the
first stage, our aim was full participation (of the woman's movement),
.... But we were diverted from our dream. And in our reaction against the
feminine mystique, which defined women solely in terms of their relation
to men as wives, mothers and homemakers, we sometimes seemed to fall into
a feminist mystique which denied that core of women's personhood that is
fulfilled through love, nurture, home." (Friedan, op.cit., 27)
So
the main emphasis in Liberal/Individualist Feminism was on removing barriers
that prevent women from competing with men on an equal footing in paid
employment. And this is still its main emphasis. Now that quite a lot of
these barriers have been removed in many countries, however, there is a
flip-side to this Liberal Feminist approach:
If
these customary and legal barriers are all removed, then if women still
don't achieve as well in public life as men do, that can be no one's fault
but the women's (a Liberal Feminist would say). You can't just look at
any inequality between men's and women's achievement in the workplace and
deduce from that that there MUST still be some outstanding barriers to
women's achievement that must be removed.
This
issue is relevant to such questions as what happens to women when they
return to the workforce after a break of several years, during which they
have been busy raising their children. Some Feminists argue that such women
should reenter the workforce at the same level of pay and seniority as
are now enjoyed by their (male and female) colleagues who have had a continuous
career throughout the period in question. I consider this Feminist position
unjust for three reasons:
First,
the employer grants seniority (in theory, anyway) not on the basis of age,
but on the basis of experience and skills gained. A person who has been
absent from the workplace has presumably not acquired that same level of
experience and skill.
Secondly,
what about people who are absent from a certain workplace for other reasons
? It would be absurd and unjust to grant them the same seniority and pay
as their colleagues who had stayed in the same workplace -- yet it would
be equally absurd and unjust to deny them this if returning mothers were
granted it!
Thirdly,
women who have children (usually) do this voluntarily, and bringing up
children is a very rewarding occupation in its own right. It is not as
if anyone was forcing them to do it. It is true that men are not usually
the ones who have to choose between children and careers, but then (on
the other hand) men are also denied the full "joys of motherhood", and
so it is only fitting and equitable that women should be unable to have
their cake and eat it too -- especially as the mothers are more likely
to be granted custody of the children after separation or divorce.
The
time eventually came when Individualist Feminism had achieved most of its
goals in Western countries. A cynic might add that Feminism was therefore
in need of new demands to make. Certainly, once a political movement has
achieved certain political gains, those gains become part of the status
quo, and the political movement involved is of course at liberty to examine
the new status quo to see if it is completely satisfied with it, or whether
it thinks further "improvements" could or should be made.
The
particular generation of activists which has struggled to achieve certain
political goals tends to rest on its laurels to some extent, but succeeding
generations grow up taking these achievements for granted, and are likely
to consider mounting new campaigns.
|
4. |
Socialist/Marxist
Feminism
I
will be discussing Socialist and Marxist Feminism together in the same
section. This is partly because they have both suffered in the world-wide
slump in Socialist and Marxist influence which resulted from the demise
of the USSR and its satellite governments in Eastern Europe. So they are
no longer important enough to be accorded separate treatment, in my view.
A further reason for lumping them together is that some people consider
that Marxist Feminism has been superceded by Socialist Feminism. Yet another
reason for lumping them together is that they are very similar to each
other:
"Whereas
socialist feminists believe that gender and class play an approximately
equal role in any explanation of women's oppression, Marxist feminists
believe that class ultimately better accounts for women's status and function(s).
Under capitalism, they say, bourgeois women will not experience the same
kind of oppression that proletarian women will. What is distinctive about
Marxist feminism, then, is that it invites every woman, whether proletarian
or bourgeois, to understand women's oppression not so much as the result
of the intentional actions of individuals but as the product of the political,
social, and economic structures associated with capitalism." (Tong 1989,39)
It
was Socialist Feminism, together with Radical Feminism (see below), which
made up the vanguard of Feminism's Second Wave. Socialism (including Marxist
Socialism/Communism) has been a very diverse movement. Yet, with few exceptions
(such as Proudhon), Socialists were in favour of Feminism from the outset.
There
were possibly two reasons for this: First, Socialism arose at a historically
later stage than Individualism, when Feminism was already an up-and-coming
ideology; and secondly Socialism was generally antagonistic to the institution
of the family. This stance was attractive to those Feminists who wanted
to free women from their traditional role in the family.
In
most forms of Socialism, there was to be no private property for the family
to own and pass on to later generations. So there would be no need to rear
children privately and so no need to tie women to the home.
One
of the most important works in the Socialist Feminist tradition was Simone
de Beauvoir's The Second Sex. Simone de Beauvoir was an Existentialist,
as well as a Marxist. Juliet Mitchell's Woman's Estate (1971) was another
influential Marxist Feminist work. She agreed with the efforts of the Radical
Feminists (see below) to encourage women to analyse their own situation,
but she thought that the results of this process of analysis would need
Marxist theory superimposed on it for it to make any sort of sense.
One
of the main issues that concerns Marxist Feminists is household work. On
the one hand, they maintain that, even when women have full-time jobs,
their household workload often remains virtually undiminished. And, on
the other hand, they argue that women's household work has been undervalued.
Women, in Capitalist societies, have been regarded as mere consumers (using
the money that their male partners earned as producers). In fact, say the
Marxist Feminists, women's household work is also productive -- in the
sense that, if women weren't doing it for free, someone would have to be
paid to do the shopping, cook, clean the house, and look after the children,
etc..
Some
Marxist Feminists consider that women are oppressed because they are seen
as being basically parasitical, in that the work they do (household work)
is easy, and of little value. They have therefore argued for the socialisation
and collectivisation of women's household work. What they want is for people
to live communally, so that child-rearing, cooking and housework are carried
out on a large scale by paid workers. This work will then acquire a monetary
value and its worth will be thereby officially acknowledged -- even if
it is still mostly women who do it.
Other
Marxist Feminists argue that a woman's household work in an individual
household should attract a wage. This wage should be paid by the government.
On the other hand, there is a further Marxist Feminist point of view, according
to which paying women to do housework has three disadvantages:
1.
It would make it more likely that women would be isolated in their own
homes. Their work would become increasingly trivialised, as more and more
labour-saving devices became available to them. They would become more
and more prey to suburban neurosis.
2.
The relationship of the woman to the rest of her family would be put onto
a commercial footing, when many Marxists would like to get away from what
they see as Capitalism's tendency to commodify everything.
3.
It would entrench the traditional sexual division of labour -- making it
more likely that men would keep on working outside the home, and women
inside the home.
|
5. |
Existentialist
Feminism
As
stated above, de Beauvoir was an Existentialist, as well as a Marxist.
This leads authors such as Tong (1989) to classify her as primarily an
Existentialist Feminist, rather than as a Marxist Feminist.
"Simone
de Beauvoir's The Second Sex, probably the key theoretical text of twentieth-
century feminism, offered an existentialist explanation of woman's situation.
De Beauvoir argued that woman is oppressed by virtue of 'otherness.' Woman
is the Other because she is not-man. Man is the self, the free, determining
being who defines the meaning of his existence, and woman is the Other,
the object whose meaning is determined for her. If woman is to become a
self, a subject, she must, like man, transcend the definitions, labels,
and essences limiting her existence. She must make herself be whatever
she wants to be." (op.cit., 6)
|
6. |
Cultural
Feminism
Most
Feminists have been at pains to show that women are equal to men, in order
to argue that they should have equal rights to men. This has usually involved
trying to prove that women are the same (or virtually the same) as men
in all relevant ways. Any significant differences were attributed to the
effect of the environment, rather than to genetic factors. This was because
it was feared that any actual differences between men and women would be
seized upon by anti-Feminists, and used to prove that they were not equal
to each other, after all.
Yet
Cultural Feminism not only sets out to show that men and women are different
from each other -- it maintains that women's values are actually superior
to those of men. It argues that women's values should replace those of
men as the dominant ones in society.
Most
Feminists have argued that what are seen to be the negative aspects of
women's behaviour are the result of socialisation, education and upbringing.
Surely, then, the supposedly "positive" aspects of "women's values" must
also be the result of such factors. This means that both the positive and
negative aspects of women's values and behaviour might vanish as a result
of the social engineering proposed by the Cultural Feminists!
Nineteenth
Century Liberal Feminists concentrated on political and legal issues. Nineteenth
Century Cultural Feminists were different, in that they examined institutions
such as religion, marriage, and the home.
The
latter type of Feminist looked beyond the achievement of political and
legal equality between women and men -- to the changes in society that
could, or should, result from such equality. The idea, simply, was that
men had been making a mess of things, and women would do a better job of
running, or helping to run the world.
Some
Cultural Feminists believed in a myth of a past Matriarchy, when pacifism,
cooperation, nonviolent settlement of differences, and a harmonious regulation
of public life were the order of the day. This was in contrast to the destruction,
tyranny, and war which are supposed to have characterised "Patriarchy".
Margaret Fuller's Woman in the Nineteenth Century (1845) was the first
significant Cultural Feminist work.
Social
Darwinism was an important influence on Cultural Feminism. This theory
applied the quasi-Darwinian notion of the "survival of the fittest" to
human societies, races, and individual people. It implied that any society
that was "successful" had achieved that success because it had characteristics
that made it "fitter" than rival societies. It tended to value highly male
aggression and competitiveness. Some Social Darwinists even favoured murderous
competition and war as appropriate selectional mechanisms.
However,
another, less-publicised vein in Social Darwinist thought foresaw a different
trend. It considered that Humanity was evolving towards a more collective
organisation, which required more cooperation, and less competition --
more altruism, and less egoism. This was the aspect of Social Darwinism
which was picked up by Charlotte Gilman's Women and Economics (1898).
The
aspect of Cultural Feminism which is still very controversial today is
its attitude towards contraception. This only became an important issue
at the beginning of the twentieth century, but in the 1870's Elizabeth
Stanton was already advocating birth control by abstinence as a means by
which women could get "control over their lives".
|
7. |
Psychoanalytic
Feminism
"Psychoanalytic
Feminists find the root of women's oppression embedded deep in her (sic)
psyche.... the Oedipus complex, the process by which the boy gives up his
first love object, mother, in order to escape castration at the hands of
father. As a result of submitting his id (or desires) to the superego (collective
social conscience), the boy is fully integrated into culture. Together
with his father he will rule over nature and woman, both of whom contain
a similar irrational power. In contrast to the boy, the girl, who has no
penis to lose, separates slowly from her first love object, mother. As
a result, the girl's integration into culture is incomplete. She exists
at the periphery or margin of culture as the one who does not rule but
is ruled, largely because ... she fears her own power." (Tong 1989, 5)
Psychoanalytic
theory, however, is highly speculative, and not disprovable enough to rate
(in my view, anyway) as a truly "scientific" theory. In addition, I find
aspects of the above picture somewhat implausible -- particularly the notion
that females are less integrated into culture than males are. Females mature
(socially, as well as sexually) earlier than males, and females typically
show a more complete internalisation of cultural norms -- i.e. they are
"better behaved" than males. The idea that nature resembles women more
than it resembles men is also highly debatable.
|
8. |
Radical
Feminism
Radical
Feminism has tended towards what Coole (1988) calls "a sort of romantic
anarchism". In other words, Radical Feminists have tended to reject the
State itself (not to mention many institutions within it), as being a patriarchal
framework. They don't consider it to be a neutral institution which mediates
between forces, the manifestation of a flexible consensus, or a forum within
whose constraints women can achieve their political goals (as Liberal Feminists
see it).
This
form of Feminism is a product of the Second Wave -- a form which took over
where the previous strands of Feminism left off. Fewer of its ideas have
so far been implemented than is the case with Individualist Feminism or
Socialist Feminism.
"...
it is radical feminism which has been most theoretically innovative, rejecting
traditional definitions of both politics and theory, while condemning all
previous political theory as patriarchal. Unlike the Marxist approach,
it has not struggled to incorporate women into a pre-existing political
framework, but instead attempts to shift our whole perception of society,
to restructure it in terms of a radically new set of woman-centred meanings.
Its aim has been to recast political identities; to reclaim language and
culture from their masculine forms; to relocate significant political power;
to reassess human nature and to challenge traditional values." (Coole 1988,
235)
The
main difference between Radical Feminism and other types of Feminism is
that the former denies any Psychological differences between the sexes.
Upbringing and education are claimed to be the causes of different male
and female behaviour-patterns, according to this view. And the function
of differential upbringing and education for men and women is supposed
to be to support the institution of male dominance (patriarchy). Radical
Feminists demand the abolition of all sexually differentiated roles and
the creation of an androgynous society.
"Some
radical feminists ... pursue the logic of their analysis to a point where
a united women's movement of the broad left becomes difficult to realize.
In their view, women's physiological capacities for reproduction are analogous
to the material production of the working class in traditional Marxism.
Women, then, constitute a class in the same way that workers do. Just as
the working class must become a class for itself by taking control of production,
so, too, must women take control of their reproduction in order to become
free. An absolute extension of the class analogy must lead to the idea
of the destruction of the previously dominant class - men; or, at least,
separation from it. Radicals demand that lesbianism be considered not merely
a matter of freedom of choice but as essential political practice for feminists."
(Meehan 1990, 191-2)
One
of the best-known Feminist works on sexuality is Germaine Greer's "The
Female Eunuch" (1971). This book is one of the classics of Radical Feminism.
It is radical in the sense that it maintains that people such as Betty
Friedan did not go far enough. Setting up a female Establishment in opposition
to the male Establishment, as Friedan suggested, did not help most women,
according to Greer.
Shulamith
Firestone's The Dialectic of Sex (1970) comes under the category of Socialist
Feminism, as well as of Radical Feminism. This book is unusually intelligent,
clear, lucid, and thorough in its approach, by the usual Feminist standards.
This does not mean, of course, that what it claims is necessarily true
or undistorted.
Firestone
bases her own analysis on the following, in part uncontroversial, assertions
to do with what she calls the "biological family":
"1)
That women throughout history before the advent of birth control were at
the continual mercy of their biology -- menstruation, menopause, and 'female
ills', constant painful childbirth, wetnursing and care of infants, all
of which made them dependent on males ... for physical survival.
2)
That human infants take an even longer time to grow up than animals, and
thus are
helpless
and, for some short period at least, dependent on adults for physical survival.
3)
That a basic mother/child interdependency has existed in some form in every
society, past or present, and thus has shaped the psychology of every mature
female and every infant.
4)
That the natural reproductive difference between the sexes led directly
to the first division of labour at the origins of class, as well as furnishing
the paradigm of caste (discrimination based on biological characteristics)"
(ibid, 8-9).
There
is a crucial vagueness at the end of this fourth point. The terms "at the
origins of" and "paradigm" seem to imply that the sexual division of labour
was a precondition for the emergence of the phenomena of class and caste.
Firestone makes this claim explicit (though she still provides no evidence
for it), in her definition of historical materialism:
"Historical
materialism is that view of the course of history which seeks the ultimate
cause and the great moving power of all historic events in the dialectic
of sex: the division of society into two distinct biological classes for
procreative reproduction, and the struggles of these classes with one another;
in the changes in the modes of marriage, reproduction and childcare created
by these struggles; in the connected development of other physically-differentiated
classes [castes]; and in the first division of labour based on sex which
developed into the [economic-cultural] class system."
Much
to her credit, Firestone pooh-poohs the efforts of some Feminists to attribute
the causes of these facts to environmental factors. She points to the near
universality of such arrangements in mankind, and other animals, as well.
If the environment is the cause, why so few exceptions?
It
is at this point that she ceases to be dispassionate or objective. She
talks of the "psychosexual distortions" in the human personality that the
above four points have brought about. She obviously has some implicit utopian
Feminist "psychosexual normality" in mind. Firestone obviously considers
that she is in a position to judge most personalities to be "distorted".
Other people, however, would not necessarily see her as being particularly
qualified to make such sweeping judgements. She simply assumes that almost
everyone's personality is "distorted", and that only she (together with,
perhaps, a few friends) is "normal".
As
is typical of Feminists, she finds this superficial argumentation sufficient
basis upon which to start talking about the "tyranny (of men, of course)
over women and children". She sees this as being biological in origin.
Modern technology, however, makes it feasible, she thinks, to overthrow
the biological basis of the present sexual power-structure.
This
is where her psychosexual utopia comes in. She argues that women should
take control of "the new population biology as well as all the social institutions
of childbearing and childrearing". More radically, in her utopia,
"genital
differences between human beings would no longer matter culturally. (A
reversion to an unobstructed pansexuality -- Freud's 'polymorphous perversity'
-- would probably supersede hetero/homo/bi-sexuality.) The reproduction
of the species by one sex for the benefit of both would be replaced by
(at least the option of) artificial reproduction: children would be born
to both sexes equally, or independently of either.... the dependence of
the child on the mother (and vice versa) would give way to a greatly shortened
dependence on a small group of others in general.... The division of labor
would be ended by the elimination of labor altogether (cybernation)." (op.cit.)
A
more traditional view of the physical differences between males and females
might be characterised as follows:
"...(1)
people are born with the hormones, anatomy, and chromosomes of either a
male or a female; (2) females are destined to have a much more burdensome
reproductive role than are males; (3) males will, other things being equal,
exhibit 'masculine' psychological traits (for example, 'assertiveness,
aggressiveness, hardiness, rationality or the ability to think logically,
abstractly and analytically, ability to control emotion'), whereas females
will, other things being equal, exhibit 'feminine' psychological traits
(for example, 'gentleness, modesty, humility, supportiveness, empathy,
compassionateness, tenderness, nurturance, intuitiveness, sensitivity,
unselfishness'); and (4) society should preserve this natural order, making
sure that its men remain 'manly' and its women 'womanly'." (Tong, op.cit.
page 3)
I am
not a doctor or biologist, but it is generally accepted, I think, that
there is a wide range of "maleness" among men, and a wide range of "femaleness"
among women, as regards anatomical characteristics and hormonal strengths.
So it is not a case of people either being 100% male or 100% female. There
are gradations of maleness and gradations of femaleness.
It
is also possible to surgically alter people's anatomy, and to alter their
internal hormone balance artificially. Germaine Greer, for example, said
on television once that she was given the male hormone testosterone as
a treatment for menopause, and she then began to drive her car aggressively
-- like a man!
The
most important issue that the Radical Feminists have raised (in my view)
is whether in fact society has a moral duty (a) to maintain the socio-biological
division between males and females, as being a good thing in its own right;
or (b) to use all biotechnological and social engineering means at its
disposal to reduce, or even eliminate the physical and social differences
between men and women -- on the grounds that these differences have been
outmoded by biotechnology and lead to social inequities; or (c) to regard
the division of its citizens into males and females as being something
of no moral significance whatsoever -- it should neither be preserved for
its own sake, nor demolished for the sake of doing so.
I
personally favour option (c). The human race has come to control its environment
to the extent that many people are worried that we are in the process of
destroying it. We may be about to reach the same turning-point as regards
our societies and our anatomies and physiologies. In areas as diverse as
animal and plant species and human cultures and languages, the trend among
the "politically correct" these days is towards the preservation of diversity
for its own sake. In the face of our growing ability to eliminate the differences
between the sexes, it may become politically correct to want to preserve
this type of diversity, as well as the other types of diversity referred
to above.
From
my point of view, it is not so much that this is a moral imperative in
its own right. My point, really, is that, once humans have the power to
change more or less every aspect of themselves, as well as of their environment,
the very purpose of human existence is called into question. One thing
that we cannot create for ourselves scientifically is the values we need
to guide our actions -- so we may end up falling back on traditional values,
for lack of anything better.
We
cannot trust Feminism alone to give us moral guidance, as we enter this
brave new world. One of the main fallacies of Feminism -- especially Radical
Feminism -- is the notion that there is something intrinsically inferior
about the woman's traditional role as housewife and mother. I think it
is partly the fact that it does not constitute paid employment -- but it
is not rational simply to assume that paid employment is necessarily more
fulfilling or valid than the family work role. Consider the value that
is being placed on longer holidays and shorter working-weeks in some countries.
If it is so desirable for working people to have less time at work, how
can it be so desirable for women to be in paid employment? These seems
to be a contradiction here.
One
of the most influential Feminist works in recent times has been Kate Millett's
Sexual Politics. Her central thesis is that one can characterise the relationship
between the sexes in political terms. This insight apparently derives originally
from Wilhelm Reich, and it seems to me to be quite correct. However, it
would be fairer to be more balanced than the Feminists are about the actual
political relationships that exist between the sexes.
Millett
starts from the following assumptions:
(a)
that the United States (and similar countries) are "patriarchies";
(b)
that this fact is evident from the fact that politicians are mainly males;
(c)
and that this rule by men over women applies to all components of society,
including the family.
She
doesn't makes these claims very clearly or explicitly, but it is evident
that she believes them to be true. Nowadays, Feminism has become established
to such an extent that these tenets are popularly regarded as virtually
self-evident throughout the western world. And Kate Millett sees them as
applying to all existing societies, not just the USA.
Two
concepts that typify Radical Feminism are the theoretical maxim that "The
Personal Is Political" and its practical corollary, "consciousness-raising".
"Within
the consciousness-raising group each person's experience, each woman's
life-story was a matter of interest. We understood that through listening
to an individual's experience we could draw a much richer picture of how
society was put together. Sexual politics provided an understanding of
how society works both at an ideological level and at a material level
and deepened the understanding the left had of human experience. The Women's
Liberation Movement built an analysis of society founded on the nuts and
bolts of individual life experience. It enlarged and challenged previous
understanding of the social, economic and political basis of society."
(Eichenbaum and Orbach: "Outside In. Inside Out. Women's Psychology: A
Feminist Psychoanalytic Account," Harmondsworth:Penguin, 1982, p. 12)
I
would liken this process to the gathering of data to prove a scientific
hypothesis, with the major difference that consciousness-raising had a
built-in bias which can be quite easily be shown up by asking the (rhetorical,
of course) question,"How many consciousness-raising groups did the Feminists
hold to enable men to discuss how they had been oppressed by women in their
lives?" In other words, "consciousness-raising" is a near-synonym to "brainwashing"
or "instruction" or "conversion". Radical Feminist theory (Sexual Politics,
as conceived of by Feminists) provided the framework for women to reinterpret
their lives -- much as religious conversion provides a new "insight".
|
9. |
Postmodern
Feminism / French Feminism
Postmodern
Feminism arose in France, under the influence of the Deconstructionist
school of Philosphy. A cynic might characterise it as a stage or type of
Feminism that makes a virtue out of the necessity that contemporary Feminism
is splintered and apparently directionless.
"Postmodern
feminists worry that because feminism purports to be an explanatory theory,
it ... is in danger of trying to provide the explanation for why woman
is oppressed, or the ten steps all women must take in order to achieve
true liberation." (Tong 1989, 217)
Feminism
is in fact unable to do these things. Indeed, no Feminist, to my knowledge,
has actually demonstrated objectively that women are (more) oppressed (than
men), and, therefore, that "liberation" is a relevant word in this context.
Such an objective demonstration is a precondition for the explanatory theory
referred to above.
I
would see the splintered nature of Postmodern Feminism as being the result
of the fact that none of the various types of Feminism discussed earlier
in this chapter has been able to construct such an explanatory theory.
In turn, this splintered condition has provided an atmosphere in which
the so-called "Backlash" has been able to emerge.
|
10. |
Women's
Studies
"Women's
Studies" is a curious sort of academic subject. Part of its strangeness
is its newness, of course -- but there is more to it than that. It has
more in common with theological or ideological training than with other
academic disciplines in (say) the Social Sciences area.
"Women's
studies, like feminism itself, presents two approaches to the question
of inequality. One approach, using anthropological, biological, historical
and psychological evidence, argues that women are essentially no different
from men, and that therefore in a differently structured society it would
be possible for divisions based upon sex or gender differences to disappear,
leaving us with an equal society. The other approach argues that women
are essentially different from men and that inequality results in an undervaluing
of female activities and characteristics.... Women's studies can thus be
seen to be linked to two concepts of equality, which we may call 'plain
equal' or 'equal but different'. The kinds of problems involved in trying
to marry the two approaches can be demonstrated by ...." (Ruth, "Issues
in Feminism: A First Course in Women's Studies." Boston: Houghton Mifflin,
1980, p. 5)
It
is a characteristic of the ideology of a social movement that it tries
to "marry together" contradictory tendencies, in an attempt to maximise
the political clout of the movement. More purely academic subjects, on
the other hand, tend to focus on contradictions in an attempt to reach
a conclusion as to which side of a controversy is correct, and which is
wrong.
It
is because Women's Studies is not really an academic subject, in this sense,
that we cannot expect it to look objectively at such questions as whether
men are oppressed in society, whether they are oppressed by women, and
whether they are oppressed more than women are. Women's Studies takes the
oppression of women (by men or by "Society") as a basic assumption or axiom
which no right-thinking person would even question.
This
bias towards political action is admitted by Women's Studies lecturers
themselves:
"...
the ideas, methods, curricula, and theories of Women's Studies exhibit
great diversity and resist easy definition. Those now working in Women's
Studies have called it variously a process, a field of inquiry, a critical
perspective, a center for social action, and/or the academic arm of the
women's movement. It is all of these and more" (ibid, p. 3).
Ruth
is aware of the charge that Women's Studies is biased. She responds to
this by claiming that male bias (which she calls "Masculine-ism", "Masculism",
or "Androcentrism") has always been a feature of Society. This may well
be so, but showing that many male academics have been biased does not logically
prove that Women's Studies is NOT biased -- nor does it justify Women's
Studies being biased, if it is.
"Feminist
criticism is revealing male bias, not creating a female one, as charged.
Women's Studies seeks to be the prophylactic of bias, not the cause" (ibid,
9).
Masculists
are not responsible for what male bias has existed and does exist. Masculists
do not need to defend male bias, where it exists. If Feminists reveal male
bias, then that is not a bad thing. However, Feminists do more than just
reveal male bias -- they also create female bias. One of the main aims
of this book is to reveal cases of female bias.
It
is also interesting to note what Ruth (1980) sees as being the goals of
her field:
"Women's
Studies seeks ...
to
change women's sense of ourselves, our self-image, our sense of worth and
rights, our presence in the world,
to
change women's aspirations, based on an increased sense of self-confidence
and self-love,
to
allow women to create for ourselves new options in our own personal goals
as well as in our commitments and/or contributions to society
to
alter the relations between women and men, to create true friendship and
respect beweeen the sexes in place of "the war between the sexes"
to
give all people, women and men, a renewed sense of human worth, to restore
to the center of human endeavors a love for beauty, kindness, justice,
and quality in living
to
reaffirm in society the quest for harmony, peace, and humane compassion"
(op.cit.,9).
Of
these goals, I would characterize the first two as arrogant, and the others
as either naive or hypocritical. What the first two goals imply is that
most women have an "incorrect" sense of themselves, and "incorrect" aspirations.
Women's Studies lecturers are, it seems, a superior breed of woman, and
they alone know what women should feel about themselves and what their
aspirations should be! It is hard to think of anyone apart from a religious
guru who would have the arrogance to claim this sort of superior knowledge.
The last two of the goals are so naive and vague as to be absurd in any
context except perhaps that of a religious cult.
It
is one thing to discover that a group is oppressed, in the sense that they
are deprived of things that they want, which other social groups are permitted
to enjoy. But it is quite another thing to be an activist who wants something
for themself, who discovers that other members of the group don't have
the same desires, and who then goes about trying to persuade them to want
the same things that he/she wants.
Where
have Women's Studies lecturers acquired these "superior" values that they
want women to adopt? The answer is that they have got them from men. Feminists
are intellectual tomboys. They have somehow internalised the idea that
what boys and men traditionally do/have done is somehow superior to (rather
than just being different from) what girls and women traditionally do/have
done. These Feminists are psychological transsexuals, and they want to
convert as many women as possible to their (i.e. men's) way of thinking,
so that they (the Feminists) will no longer seem to be a peculiar minority.
In Western countries, they have largely succeeded.
To
claim that Feminists want to end the "war between the sexes" is simply
hypocritical: Feminists started the war, and the only conditions under
which they would be willing to end the "war" would be total victory for
themselves. In fact, I don't think there is a realistic possibility of
any society ever reaching a state of affairs which would satisfy all Feminists. |
2002
Version
MANIFESTATIONS
OF FEMINISM
Introduction
This
chapter gives a brief survey of some historical forms of Feminism. It is
not intended primarily as an attack on Feminism, because that has been
the function of the rest of this book. Rather, it is to give an historical
account of the Feminist ideology and political movement, which has also
been known as the Women's Liberation Movement, or the Women's Movement.
The difference between these terms is that the word "Feminism" is sometimes
used to refer purely to a theory or ideology, whereas the terms "Women's
Movement" and "Women's Liberation Movement" also refer to political activities.
Individualist/Liberal
Feminism
Individualist
Feminism received its first substantial formulation in Mary Wollstonecraft's
A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792). This was in the tradition
of 18th century Individualist social and political theory, deriving ultimately
from John Locke's Second Treatise of Government (1689), according to which
the supreme law was to be the welfare of the people. It was a fairly small
step from that stated principle to looking at various categories of people
– such as women – and asking what the "system" was doing to or for them.
From our vantage-point, we might question the bias of the people who decided
what categories of people to investigate, but that is another issue.
Wollstonecraft
noted that when people referred to "people" or "humans," they almost always
meant men. Women were viewed principally in relation to men; i.e., as sexual
partners and rearers of men's children, and so on. She asserted women must
be looked on primarily as people in their own right, and only secondarily
as the housekeepers and wives, etc. of men.
An
important contention in her book is that men used education to train girls
to play the dependent "womanly" roles men have mapped out for them. This,
indeed, is a recurrent theme throughout the Feminist literature. Wollstonecraft
demands equality of civil rights between men and women. She does not say
much about political rights for women, though there are indications she
intended to write something on that topic, too.
John
Stuart Mill's The Subjection of Women was an important 19th Century Feminist
work, written under the influence of his late wife, Harriet Taylor. Mill's
proposals are similar to those of Wollstonecraft. But he goes further,
saying that women should have the vote. As far as employment is concerned,
he too says women should be free to enter the occupation of their choice
(including marriage and child-rearing, if that is their preferred option).
Fundamental
to Mill's philosophy, Utilitarianism, is the idea of optimizing the greatest
good for the greatest number of people; that is, ethical priority was accorded
to the greatest good of the greatest number of people. According to most
authorities on Mill's works, the notion of "equality," which is so basic
to Feminist writings in general, did not seem to obviously follow from
Utilitarian principles. It is not logically necessary that "equality" between
different groups or individuals in Society would inevitably be a means
of producing the greatest good to the greatest number of people.
It
might be argued, for example, that some people are better at producing
wealth than others. Therefore, if you want to maximise the wealth in a
given Society, you have to accord special rights and privileges to such
people in order to attain your overall goal of maximising the material
well-being of the population as a whole. Mill had to add the principle
of equality on almost as an afterthought before he could construct his
Feminist argument.
Nevertheless,
he does try to demonstrate how everybody would benefit from granting women
legal equality with men by arguing that the liberation of women will result
in a net gain in the quantity of happiness for mankind. This is because,
according to Locke's previous work, the "servitude" of women in marriage
makes many of them miserable. He also says that mankind (by which he meant,
in present day Feminist parlance, "humankind") will benefit if woman's
full potential is freed, educated, and employed to the benefit of all.
And marriages would be happier if men and women were equally well educated.
He believed happiness in marriage depended on the partners being as similar
and unified as possible.
In
the course of the nineteenth century, Feminists obtained greater educational
opportunities in schools and universities and the admission of women to
the professions. Laws relating to divorce, the property rights of married
women, and control of children in marriage were also modified in a direction
that favoured women. Moreover, by the early 20th Century, at the latest,
women gained the franchise in most western countries. The first breakthrough
for the Feminists came in 1869, when women got the vote in the American
State of Wyoming, and the first sovereign state to grant women the vote
was New Zealand – in 1893. However, in no country did men force women to
become liable to be drafted into the front line, in return for getting
the vote. This shows how little thinking was done about equality of rights
and responsibilities.
After
the franchise for women had been achieved in many countries, the Second
World War intervened. This possibly caused a hiatus in the Feminists' political
struggles, perhaps because they did not want to be forced to serve as front-line
soldiers. Such an obligation might reasonably be expected of them had they
continued agitating during the war. And when the war was over, people needed
time to forget the men who had lost their lives and/or limbs in the War.
But
sure enough, after a decent interval, a peacetime mentality soon evolved
in western societies to which the hypocrisy of some of the Feminist demands
for "equality" did not seem so glaringly obvious. This was no conspiracy
– the process is a natural one, as most people prefer to treat war as a
bad dream they want to wake up from as soon as possible! And from a Lesbian
Feminist perspective, men are always expendable.
This
postwar period marked Feminism's true Second Wave, a time when it seemed
natural to focus more and more on the way women's role in the family prevented
them from having careers to the extent men did. This attitude implied that
the roles of wife and mother were somehow inferior to that of income-earner
in a workplace (or wage-slave in the rat-race, as others might phrase it).
One
book pushing this line within the Individualist Feminist tradition was
Betty Friedan's The Feminine Mystique (1963), which followed relatively
closely on the heels of Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex (1953) (see
below). Friedan's aim was for society and women's lives to be organised
to maximise the ability of women to have a career as well as a family.
She thought that American middle-class, suburban, white, heterosexual housewives
were bound to feel unfulfilled and bored, unless they had a full-time job
outside the home:
“Science
should not relieve housewives of too much drudgery; it must concentrate
instead on creating the illusion of that sense of achievement that housewives
seem to need.” (The Feminine Mystique, 4th Dell Printing, June 1964, p
172)
This
would, of course, not be such a problem in countries and social classes
where labour-saving devices were unaffordable. But what is most interesting
here is how Friedan seems to take it for granted any sense of achievement
felt by housewives would be necessarily an "illusion". This is a very subjective
view. Obviously, Friedan obviously does not feel that a sense of achievement
in a career outside the home would be illusory – either for men or women.
Nor does she believe a woman can be both feminine and fully human:
“(B)y
choosing femininity over the painful growth to full identity, by never
achieving the hard core of self that comes not from fantasy but from mastering
reality, these girls are doomed to suffer ultimately that bored, diffuse
feeling of purposelessness, nonexistence, noninvolvement with the world
that can be called anomie, or lack of identity, or merely felt as the problem
that has no name.” (The Feminine Mystique, 4th Dell Printing, June 1964,
p 172)
This
is the same gender-role confusion which has affected many Feminists; somehow,
they manage to equate femininity with a lack of a identity. What this really
demonstrates is the frustration that bisexual middle-class Feminist writers
felt with the need to conform to "feminine" role-models, and why they wanted
to convert more women to their more masculine personalities. They wanted
to take power away from the feminine and attractive women, whose personas
were centred around cooperating with men, and create a cohort of women
whose personas would centre around competing with men. Overtly Lesbian
Feminists are merely at the extreme end of this covertly Lesbian movement.
From this perspective, Friedan's famous "problem that has no name" is actually
the "problem" of heterosexuality – it couldn't be given a name because
its true name would repel converts. Despite this, some found her less radical
than her predecessors:
Betty
Friedan's 1963 book, The Feminine Mystique, was in some ways less 'radical'
than Wollstonecraft's, Taylor's or Mill's. Despite Friedan's implicit understanding
of woman as a powerless sex class, she often wrote as if individual women
can, through sheer effort, advance to the ranks of the powerful sex class
known as 'man'. Her tendency, at least in The Feminine Mystique, was to
forget that this is easier said than done, so long as men are generally
in charge of hiring and promoting. (Tong 1989, 22)
Tong
believes Friedan's emphasis on individual "self-improvement" constitutes
a diversion from radical activity aimed at changing society through political
means, and criticises Friedan for not being analytical enough to look for
barriers to women achieving careers outside the home. Many years later,
however, Friedan remedied this omission to some extent with a second book,
The Second Stage:
“In
the first stage, our aim was full participation (of the woman's movement),
... But we were diverted from our dream. And in our reaction against the
feminine mystique, which defined women solely in terms of their relation
to men as wives, mothers and homemakers, we sometimes seemed to fall into
a feminist mystique which denied that core of women's personhood that is
fulfilled through love, nurture, home.” (Friedan, op. cit., 27)
So
the main emphasis in Liberal/Individualist Feminism was on removing barriers
that prevent women from competing with men on an equal footing in paid
employment. And this remains its main emphasis, although many of these
barriers no longer exist. Ironically, a strict interpretation of the Liberal/Individualist
Feminists paradigm does not sit well with the dominant Feminist thinking
today: If women still don't achieve as well in public life as men do, responsibility
rests solely with the individual (a Liberal Feminist would say). You can't
just look at any inequality between men's and women's achievement in the
workplace and deduce from it that there must still be some sexist barriers
to women's achievement.
This
issue is relevant to such questions as what happens to women when they
return to the workforce after a break of several years, during which they
have been busy raising their children. Some Feminists argue such women
should reenter the workforce at the same level of pay and seniority as
enjoyed by their (male and female) colleagues who had a continuous career
throughout the period in question. I consider this Feminist position unjust
for three reasons:
First,
the employer grants seniority (in theory, anyway) not on the basis of age,
but experience and skills gained. A person who has been absent from the
workplace has presumably not acquired the same level of experience and
skill. Feminists respond that being a mother provides much relevant experience
and skill – but this is a brain-dead argument. It depends on what occupations
are involved.
Obviously,
being a mother is somewhat relevant to a career as an au pair, nanny, cook,
nurse, or childcare worker. However, it is irrelevant to a career as an
office-worker, laboratory technician, police officer or miner! An analysis
of the relevant job description can be conducted by any halfway intelligent
person, then compared with that of a housewife/mother. Anyone who buys
the blanket Feminist argument that being a mother is equally relevant to
any occupation should not be allowed to handle sharp implements, operate
a motor vehicle or occupy any position requiring more than rudimentary
reasoning ability. Their argument reeks of intellectual incompetence.
Second,
what about people who are absent from a certain workplace for other reasons?
It would be absurd and unjust to grant them the same seniority and pay
as their colleagues who had stayed in the same workplace – yet it would
be equally absurd and unjust to deny them this while granting it to returning
mothers.
Finally,
women who have children (usually) do this voluntarily, and bringing up
children is a very rewarding occupation in its own right. It is not as
if anyone was forcing them to do it. Those Feminists who believe all men
are involved in a pervasive patriarchal conspiracy to subjugate all women
are paranoid.
Certainly,
some men derive satisfaction from being the breadwinner and being waited
on hand-and-foot by women, and some men and women actively promote this
vision of Society. But that is a quid pro quo arrangement – the man has
burdens he must carry in wartime and other emergencies. It is also true
that men are usually not the ones who have to choose between children and
careers; on the other hand, men are also denied some of the joys of motherhood,
so it is only equitable that women should be unable to have their cake
and eat it too – especially as the mothers are more likely to be granted
custody of the children after separation or divorce.
The
time came when Individualist Feminism achieved most of its goals in western
countries. A cynic might add that Feminism was therefore in need of new
demands to make. Certainly, once a political movement has achieved certain
political gains, those gains become part of the status quo and the political
movement involved is at liberty to examine the new status quo to see if
it is completely satisfied with it, or whether it thinks further "improvements"
could or should be made.
Generally,
when activists achieve their political goals they tend to rest on their
laurels to some extent, and there is often a hiatus until succeeding generations
grow up taking these achievements for granted and consider mounting new
campaigns. However, the recent institutionalisation and financing of perpetual
Feminism through Women's Studies departments, Ministries of Women's Affairs
and state-funded and privately sponsored women's organisations are countering
this tendency.
Socialist/Marxist
Feminism
Socialist
and Marxist Feminism are very similar to each other as Tong explains:
“Whereas
socialist feminists believe that gender and class play an approximately
equal role in any explanation of women's oppression, Marxist feminists
believe that class ultimately better accounts for women's status and function(s).
Under capitalism, they say, bourgeois women will not experience the same
kind of oppression that proletarian women will. What is distinctive about
Marxist feminism, then, is that it invites every woman, whether proletarian
or bourgeois, to understand women's oppression not so much as the result
of the intentional actions of individuals but as the product of the political,
social, and economic structures associated with capitalism.” (Tong 1989,39)
It
was Socialist Feminism, together with Radical Feminism (see below), which
made up the vanguard of Feminism's Second Wave. Socialism (including Marxist
Socialism/Communism) has been a very diverse movement. Yet, with few exceptions
(such as the French writer Proudhon), Socialists favoured Feminism from
the outset. There were possibly two reasons for this: First, Socialism
arose at a historically later stage than Individualism, when Feminism was
already an up-and-coming ideology; second, Socialism was generally antagonistic
to the institution of the family. This was attractive to those Feminists
who wanted to disconnect women from their role in the family.
In
most forms of Socialism, there was to be no private property for the family
to own and pass on to later generations. So there would be no need to rear
children privately or tie women to the home.
One
of the most important works in the Socialist Feminist tradition was Simone
de Beauvoir's The Second Sex. Influenced by Jean-Paul Sartre, she was an
Existentialist as well as a Marxist. Juliet Mitchell's Woman's Estate (1971)
was another influential Marxist Feminist work. She agreed with the efforts
of the Radical Feminists (see below) to encourage women to analyse their
own situation, but she thought the results of this process of analysis
would need Marxist theory superimposed on it for it to make any sort of
sense.
One
of the main issues concerning Marxist Feminists is household work. They
maintain that even when women have full-time jobs their household workload
remains both undiminished and undervalued: if women weren't doing it for
free, someone would have to be paid to do the shopping, cook, clean the
house, and look after the children, etc. But capitalist societies, they
contend, view women as mere consumers (using the money their male partners
earn as producers).
Some
Marxist Feminists believe women are oppressed because they see women as
basically parasitical, the work of a housewife as easy, and of little value.
They have therefore argued for the socialisation and collectivisation of
women's household work. What they want is for people to live communally,
so child-rearing, cooking and housework are carried out on a large scale
by paid workers. This work will then acquire a monetary value and its worth
will be thereby officially acknowledged – even if it is still mostly women
who do it.
Other
Marxist Feminists argue that a woman's household work in an individual
household should attract a wage. This wage should be paid by the government.
According to Tong (1989), however, there is another Marxist Feminist point
of view which has it that paying women to do housework has three disadvantages:
1. |
It
would make it more likely that women would be isolated in their own homes.
Their work would become increasingly trivialised, as more and more labour-saving
devices became available to them. They would become more and more prey
to suburban neurosis. |
2. |
The
relationship of the woman to the rest of her family would be put onto a
commercial footing, when many Marxists would like to get away from what
they see as Capitalism's tendency to commodify everything. |
3. |
It
would entrench the traditional sexual division of labour – making it more
likely that men would keep on working outside the home, and women inside
the home. |
Existentialist
Feminism
As
stated above, de Beauvoir was both an Existentialist and a Marxist. This
leads authors such as Tong (1989) to classify her as primarily an Existentialist
Feminist, rather than as a Marxist Feminist.
To
fully understand Existentialist Feminism, one would have to understand
Existentialism, and it would be outside the scope of this book to digress
into the details of Existential theory. However, the essential characteristic
of Existentialist Feminism is that it takes the positive, active categories
of Existentialism and applies them to men, and takes the negative, passive
categories and applies them to women – thus making women out to be disadvantaged
and oppressed.
“Simone
de Beauvoir's The Second Sex, probably the key theoretical text of twentieth-century
Feminism, offered an existentialist explanation of woman's situation. De
Beauvoir argued that woman is oppressed by virtue of otherness. Woman is
the Other because she is not-man. Man is the self, the free, determining
being who defines the meaning of his existence, and woman is the Other,
the object whose meaning is determined for her. If woman is to become a
self, a subject, she must, like man, transcend the definitions, labels,
and essences limiting her existence. She must make herself be whatever
she wants to be.” (Tong, op. cit., 6).
Cultural
Feminism
Margaret
Fuller's Woman in the Nineteenth Century (1845) was the first significant
Cultural Feminist work. Cultural Feminism sets out to persuade us that
men and women are not only different from each other, but that women's
values are superior to men's and women's values should supplant men's values.
In other words, this is Female Supremacism.
What
about women who behave badly? Most Feminists insist such are the result
of socialisation, education and upbringing in a patriarchal society. By
the same logic, however, the supposedly "positive" aspects of "women's
values" must also derive from the same source. This means both the positive
and negative aspects of women's values and behaviour might vanish as a
result of the social engineering proposed by the Cultural Feminists!
Where
19th century Liberal Feminists concentrated on political and legal issues,
Cultural Feminists examined institutions such as religion, marriage, and
the home. They looked beyond the possibility of political and legal equality
between women and men to the changes in society they believed could or
should result from such equality. The idea, simply, was that men had been
making a mess of things and women would do a better job of running, or
helping to run the world.
Some
Cultural Feminists believe in the myth of a primordial matriarchy, when
pacifism, cooperation, nonviolent settlement of differences, and a harmonious
regulation of public life were the order of the day -- in contrast to the
destruction, tyranny, and war which are supposed to have characterised
patriarchy. By using the word myth, I don't mean this belief is necessarily
incorrect – just that it is an unproved tale about historical events which
is central to a particular explanation of Society.
Unable
to find any "Matriarchies" in the present day, many Feminists resort to
inventing an idyllic Lost Matriarchal Paradise in the dim mists of prehistory.
Even though there is no acceptable scholarly evidence for this, it has
become an accepted fact in 'Women's Studies'. (www.patriarchy.com/~sheaffer/patriarchy.html)
Social
Darwinism (Spencer, 1851) was an important influence on Cultural Feminism.
This theory applied the quasi-Darwinian notion of the "survival of the
fittest" to human societies, races and individual people. It implied that
any successful society achieved its success by virtue of characteristics
that made it "fitter" than rival societies. Societies could be "fitter"
in various ways, including:
1.
birthrate;
2.
infant mortality rate;
3.
longevity;
4.
food production;
5.
total population;
6.
total land area;
7.
success in warfare, etc.
Social
Darwinism placed high value on male aggression and competitiveness. Some
Social Darwinists even favoured murderous competition and war as appropriate
selective mechanisms. However, another, less-publicised school of Social
Darwinist thought, such as Charlotte Gilman's Women and Economics (1898),
foresaw a different trend. They believed Humanity was evolving toward a
more collective organisation, requiring more cooperation and less competition,
more altruism and less egoism.
Psychoanalytic
Feminism
The
core thinking of Psychoanalytic Feminism goes something like this:
“Psychoanalytic
Feminists find the root of women's oppression embedded deep in her (sic)
psyche.... the Oedipus complex, the process by which the boy gives up his
first love object, mother, in order to escape castration at the hands of
father. As a result of submitting his id (or desires) to the superego (collective
social conscience), the boy is fully integrated into culture. Together
with his father he will rule over nature and woman, both of whom contain
a similar irrational power. In contrast to the boy, the girl, who has no
penis to lose, separates slowly from her first love object, mother. As
a result, the girl's integration into culture is incomplete. She exists
at the periphery or margin of culture as the one who does not rule but
is ruled, largely because ... she fears her own power.” (Tong 1989, 5)
Psychoanalytic
theory, however, is highly speculative, and not disprovable enough to rate
(in my view, anyway) as a truly "scientific" theory. In addition, I find
aspects of the above picture somewhat implausible -- particularly the notion
that females are less integrated into culture than males. Females mature
(socially, as well as sexually) earlier than males, and females typically
show a more complete internalisation of cultural norms – i.e., they are
"better behaved" – than males. Society really reflects female values more
than male values and directs male behaviours toward supporting and protecting
females. The idea that nature resembles women more than men is also highly
debatable.
Radical
Feminism
Radical
Feminists tend to reject the State itself, not to mention many institutions
within it, as a patriarchal framework. They believe it is neither a neutral
institution which mediates between forces – the result of a flexible consensus
– nor a forum within whose constraints women can achieve their political
goals (as Liberal Feminists see it).
Radical
Feminism is a product of the Second Wave and took over where previous factions
left off. Fewer of its ideas have been implemented than is the case with
Individualist Feminism or Socialist Feminism, however:
“(I)t
is radical feminism which has been most theoretically innovative, rejecting
traditional definitions of both politics and theory, while condemning all
previous political theory as patriarchal. Unlike the Marxist approach,
it has not struggled to incorporate women into a preexisting political
framework, but instead attempts to shift our whole perception of society,
to restructure it in terms of a radically new set of woman-centred meanings.
Its aim has been to recast political identities; to reclaim language and
culture from their masculine forms; to relocate significant political power;
to reassess human nature and to challenge traditional values. (Coole, D.
H., 1988: Women in Political Theory, p. 235)”
The
main difference between Radical Feminism and other types of Feminism is
that the former denies any Psychological differences between the sexes.
Upbringing and education are claimed to be the causes of different male
and female behaviour patterns, according to this view. And the function
of differential upbringing and education for men and women is supposed
to be to support the institution of male dominance (patriarchy). Radical
Feminists demand the abolition of all sexually differentiated roles and
the creation of an androgynous society. Needless to say, this is a philosophy
created by lesbians to suit Lesbians.
“Some
radical feminists ... pursue the logic of their analysis to a point where
a united women's movement of the broad left becomes difficult to realize.
In their view, women's physiological capacities for reproduction are analogous
to the material production of the working class in traditional Marxism.
Women, then, constitute a class in the same way that workers do. Just as
the working class must become a class for itself by taking control of production,
so, too, must women take control of their reproduction in order to become
free. An absolute extension of the class analogy must lead to the idea
of the destruction of the previously dominant class – men; or, at least,
separation from it. Radicals demand that lesbianism be considered not merely
a matter of freedom of choice but as essential political practice for feminists.”
(Meehan, Elizabeth (1990): British Feminism from the 1960s to the 1980s.
pp. 191-2)
One
of the best-known Feminist works on sexuality is Germaine Greer's The Female
Eunuch (1971). This book is one of the classics of Radical Feminism. It
is radical in the sense that it claims that people such as Betty Friedan
did not go far enough. Setting up a female Establishment in opposition
to the male Establishment, as Friedan suggested, did not help most women,
according to Greer.
Shulamith
Firestone's The Dialectic of Sex (1970) comes under the category of Socialist
Feminism as well as Radical Feminism. This book is unusually intelligent,
clear, lucid, and thorough in its approach, by Feminist standards. This
does not mean that what it claims is true or undistorted. She eventually
ended up in a psychiatric institution, and I don't find this very surprising.
Shulamith
Firestone is one influential Feminist writer who used Marxism as a starting-point.
She begins by citing the 19th Century German Communist theorist Engels
with approval, though she thinks he did not go far enough:
Engels
did observe that the original division of labor was between man and woman
for the purposes of child-breeding; that within the family the husband
was the owner, the wife the means of production, the children the labor;
and that reproduction of the human species was an important economic system
distinct from the means of production. (Firestone, The Dialectic of Sex,
1971, New York: Bantam, pp. 4-5)
Even
if we take a narrow, purely physical view of reproduction, Engels' analysis
is very distorted. The male, along with the female, is part of the means
of sexual production. And many acts of sexual intercourse are usually required
for each fertilisation. Moreover, the male usually expends much more energy
in these acts of coitus than does the female. If there is foreplay, the
man is typically much more energetic in this phase of intercourse as well
as in the actual coitus.
Additionally,
the ultimate "owner" of the children varies greatly from culture to culture,
and time to time. The ultimate test, I would say, is who gets custody of
the children in cases of separation or divorce. In the western world, this
is almost always the mother. Thus, in the contemporary western world, at
least, women are the real "owners" of the "product." In about ninety percent
of cases, according to the consensus of fathers' rights activists on the
Internet, mothers gets sole custody of their children after a divorce or
separation. This bias against fathers often takes the form of the "Natural
Caretaker Doctrine" – the belief that the person who has the most day-to-day
contact with children is the person best suited to have custody after separation
or divorce.
It
is a well documented fact that fathers have a very difficult time obtaining
custody due to the pervasive anti-father prejudice that still exists in
many parts of the Family Court system. (www.deltabravo.net/custody/index.shtml).
What's
more, reproduction properly includes all the years devoted to rearing (feeding,
housing, educating, etc.) the children. Typically, as the primary breadwinner,
fathers expend a substantial proportion of their time and income for that
purpose. If, as argued above, it is the mother who is the real "owner"
of the children, then it is really the mother who is exploiting the father
in this particular economic system. When you get right down to it, men
are an oppressed minority in western society today. They are a genuine
minority, unlike women, who are a privileged majority dressed up by Feminists
as an oppressed minority.
Firestone
thought that where Radical Feminism and human biology disagreed, it had
to be human biology that gave way! In other words, she was lucid enough
to see some conflicts between Radical Feminist theory and reality, but
like so many other ideologues tilting at windmills, she didn't let that
stop her. More recent Feminists have solved such problems by lying about
the facts and bullying entire societies into believing arrant nonsense
(as we have seen in previous chapters). When entire societies believe lies,
this is called "ideology," "superstition" or "religion".
Firestone
bases her own analysis on the following, in part uncontroversial, assertions
to do with what she calls the "biological family":
1. |
That
women throughout history before the advent of birth control were at the
continual mercy of their biology – menstruation, menopause, and 'female
ills', constant painful childbirth, wet nursing and care of infants, all
of which made them dependent on males ... for physical survival. |
2. |
That
human infants take an even longer time to grow up than animals, and thus
are helpless and, for some short period at least, dependent on adults for
physical survival. |
3. |
That
a basic mother/child interdependency has existed in some form in every
society, past or present, and thus has shaped the psychology of every mature
female and every infant. |
4. |
That
the natural reproductive difference between the sexes led directly to the
first division of labour at the origins of class, as well as furnishing
the paradigm of caste (discrimination based on biological characteristics)
(ibid, 8-9). |
The
terms "at the origins of" and "paradigm" seem to imply the sexual division
of labour was a precondition for the emergence of the phenomena of class
and caste. Firestone makes this claim explicit (though she still provides
no evidence for it) in her definition of historical materialism:
Modern
technology makes it feasible, she thinks, to overthrow the biological basis
of the present sexual power-structure. This is where her psychosexual utopia
comes in. She argues that women should take control of "the new population
biology as well as all the social institutions of childbearing and child
rearing." More radically, in her utopia there would be no such thing as
family or community, but only disconnected individuals toiling for the
moment:
“(G)enital
differences between human beings would no longer matter culturally. (A
reversion to an unobstructed pansexuality -- Freud's 'polymorphous perversity'
– would probably supersede hetero/homo/bi-sexuality.) The reproduction
of the species by one sex for the benefit of both would be replaced by
(at least the option of) artificial reproduction: children would be born
to both sexes equally, or independently of either.... the dependence of
the child on the mother (and vice versa) would give way to a greatly shortened
dependence on a small group of others in general.... The division of labor
would be ended by the elimination of labor altogether (cybernation).” (op.
cit.)
One
of the most influential Feminist works in recent times has been Kate Millett's
Sexual Politics. Her central thesis is that one can characterise the relationship
between the sexes in political terms. This insight apparently derives originally
from Wilhelm Reich. It would be fairer to be more balanced than the Feminists
are about the actual political relationships that exist between the sexes.
Millett starts from the following assumptions:
a) |
the
United States (and similar countries) are "patriarchies"; |
b) |
this
is evident from the fact that politicians are mainly males; |
c) |
this
rule by men over women applies to all components of society, including
the family. |
She
doesn't makes these claims very clearly or explicitly, but it is evident
she believes them. And Feminism has become established to such an extent
that these tenets are popularly regarded as virtually self-evident throughout
the western world.
Two
concepts that typify Radical Feminism are the theoretical maxim "the personal
is political" and its practical corollary, "consciousness-raising".
“Within
the consciousness-raising group each person's experience, each woman's
life-story was a matter of interest. We understood that through listening
to an individual's experience we could draw a much richer picture of how
society was put together. Sexual politics provided an understanding of
how society works both at an ideological level and at a material level
and deepened the understanding the left had of human experience. The Women's
Liberation Movement built an analysis of society founded on the nuts and
bolts of individual life experience. It enlarged and challenged previous
understanding of the social, economic and political basis of society.”
(Luise Eichenbaum and Susie Orbach: Outside In. Inside Out. Women's Psychology:
A Feminist Psychoanalytic Account, Harmondsworth:Penguin,1982,12)
I would
liken this process to the gathering of data to prove a scientific hypothesis,
with the major difference that consciousness-raising has a built-in bias
which can be easily demonstrated by asking the (rhetorical, of course)
question, "How many consciousness-raising groups did the Feminists hold
to enable men to discuss how they had been oppressed by women in their
lives?" In other words, "consciousness-raising" is a near-synonym to "brainwashing,"
"instruction" or "conversion." Radical Feminist theory (sexual politics,
as conceived of by Feminists) provided the framework for women to reinterpret
their lives much as religions do for converts.
Postmodern
Feminism / French Feminism
A
cynic might characterise Postmodern Feminism as a stage or type of Feminism
that makes a virtue of the fact that contemporary Feminism is splintered
and apparently directionless:
Postmodern
feminists worry that because feminism purports to be an explanatory theory,
it ... is in danger of trying to provide the explanation for why woman
is oppressed, or the ten steps all women must take in order to achieve
true liberation. (Tong 1989, 217)
Feminism
is unable to do these things. Indeed, no Feminist has objectively demonstrated
that women are (more) oppressed (than men) and, therefore need to be "liberated."
Such an objective demonstration is a precondition for the explanatory theory
they lack. The splintered nature of Postmodern Feminism is the inevitable
result of the fact that none of the various factions of Feminism have been
able to construct an explanatory theory. In turn, these schisms have created
an environment in which the so-called "backlash" has been able to emerge.
Women's
Studies
"Women's
Studies" is a curious academic subject. Partly because it is new, but mostly
because it has more in common with theological or ideological training
than with other academic disciplines in (say) the Social Sciences.
“Women's
studies, like feminism itself, presents two approaches to the question
of inequality. One approach, using anthropological, biological, historical
and psychological evidence, argues that women are essentially no different
from men, and that therefore in a differently structured society it would
be possible for divisions based upon sex or gender differences to disappear,
leaving us with an equal society. The other approach argues that women
are essentially different from men and that inequality results in an undervaluing
of female activities and characteristics.... Women's studies can thus be
seen to be linked to two concepts of equality, which we may call 'plain
equal' or 'equal but different'.” (Ruth, Issues in Feminism: A First Course
in Women's Studies, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1980, p. 5)
It
is a characteristic of the ideology of a social movement that it tries
to "marry" contradictions in an attempt to maximise the political clout
of the movement. Purely academic disciplines, on the other hand, tend to
focus on contradictions in an attempt to reach a conclusion as to which
theory is correct.
Because
Women's Studies is not really an academic subject, however, we cannot expect
it to objectively examine such questions as whether men are oppressed in
society, whether they are oppressed by women, and whether they are oppressed
more than women. Women's Studies takes the oppression of women (by men
or by "Society") as a self-evident truth which no right-thinking person
would even question. Even Women's Studies lecturers admit this bias toward
political action rather than rigorous scholarship:
(T)he
ideas, methods, curricula, and theories of Women's Studies exhibit great
diversity and resist easy definition. Those now working in Women's Studies
have called it variously a process, a field of inquiry, a critical perspective,
a center for social action, and/or the academic arm of the women's movement.
It is all of these and more. (ibid, p. 3).
Ruth
is aware of the charge that Women's Studies is biased. She responds by
claiming male bias (which she calls "Masculine-ism," "Masculism" or "Androcentrism")
has always been a feature of Society. This may well be so, but proving
many male academics have been biased does not prove Women's Studies is
not biased, nor does it justify Women's Studies being biased, if it is.
Masculists/Men's
Rights activists are not responsible for what male bias has existed and
does exist. We do not need to defend male bias, where it exists. If Feminists
reveal male bias, that is not a bad thing. However, Feminists do more than
just reveal male bias, they also create female bias. One of the main aims
of this book is to reveal cases of female bias. Here are some of the examples
covered in this book:
1. |
the
definition of political power and identifying who has it; |
2. |
attitudes
toward male as against female circumcision; |
3. |
evaluating
male and female courtship roles in the context of rape legislation; |
4. |
the
dissemination and interpretation of the facts of domestic violence; |
5. |
the
dissemination of information on various types of child abuse; |
6. |
the
evaluation of the legal system's treatment of men and women; |
7. |
the
evaluation of employment issues involving men and women; |
8. |
the
compilation and dissemination of UN and other statistics on gender equity; |
9. |
the
choice of issues where gender equity is demanded; |
10. |
the
definition of gender equity. |
 |
Last
Update: 28 December 2004
|
 |
©Peter Zohrab |